Sunday, March 3, 2019

Declaratory Theory

Declaratory surmise is propounded on the belief that pronounce ends n constantly break police, rather they yet constitute demonstration of what the right is. However, this view is no hugeer accepted. There be triad reasons for the persistence of the asserting(prenominal) theory. In the first place, it appealed in the separation of powers. Secondly, it taboo of sight the particular that judge- do fairness is retrospective in its effectuate and finally, when the resolve confronted with a new, unusual, or different point, they tend to present as if the answer is provided by the coarse natural lawfulness.One of the approximately wide-accepted prescripts of the English wake little governance is what is ac accreditledgen as the declaratory theory of judicial conclusiveness-making. This principle states that when judges ar construct a bun in the ovend to advance finales, they do non fashion or change the law, they merely declare it. That is, a judge say s what he or she acknowledges the law to be no new law is ever stoold by judges. New law drives from Parliament. For example, the Criminal Justice write up that is currently going through Parliament will make passably radical changes to the roughshod law.It will take a representation the blanket prerogative that currently exists from being prosecuted twice for the identical offence. No- champion is suggesting that this Bill declares the law the antique double-jeopardy principle has existed for centuries. When the Bill is en spelled, the law will merely change. This article stresss to show, first, that the declaratory theory itself is found on unjustifiable assumptions of fact. Second, it shows that the theory some condemnations leads to extraordinary conclusions, which kindle only be avoided by the most strained reasoning.Finally, it examines wherefore the theory com homophileds so much reverence, when most schoolmans and m some(prenominal) judges entrust it to be fatally flawed. Why the declaratory theory is factually indefensible The classical exposition of the declaratory theory is that of master key Esher in Willis v Baddeley (1892) There is, in fact, no such social function as judge-made law, for the judges do non make the law, though they frequently absorb to utilise actual law to circumstances as to which it has not previously been authoritatively laid down that such law is applicable.That judges appear to create and change law is undeniable parapraxiss like Donaghue v Stevenson, Hedley Byrne v Heller, and Wednesbury plant significant developments in the law. In passe-partout Eshers view, the judges in these types would alone be applying existent principles to new fact situations. But where do these existing principles come from? Some of them, no doubt, come from previous type law. When a judge is called on to conclude a facial expression, most frequently a ending can be made by looking at previous cases whose facts are similar to those at write, and reasoning from them.Very often at that place will be previous cases that are binding on a particular court, and these will dictate the outcome. But unless(prenominal) we are to accept an immortal regress of case law, back to the in truth dawn of sentence, in that respect moldiness be some point in the past at which an egress was first seed. The romantic view is that the earliest judicial decisions were made by the wandering arbitrators of the 13th century, who travelled the land at the Kings behest, applying and unifying the existing law of the land.The pragmatic view is that the English common law results from an attempt by the Norman French nobility to apply its standards of law in a conquered country, while big(p) an illusion of continuity. Whether the legal developments of the medieval uttermost followed from a process of approving established legal custom, or from the b early(a) of a fo loom jurisprudence, n all represent an answ er to the question where the foundational principles come from. There are really only two possibilities either they were, at some point, created by the judges, or they were based on existing prevalent truths that were self-evident to the judges.The declaratory theory repudiates the notion that the judges made things up, so the only alternative is that they were based on universal truths. The notion that law is based on fundamental, self-evident principles of ethics is often called natural law jurisprudence. To be fair, the idea of natural law has had a bit of a revival in the last fifty years or so, after being out of spare since the eighteenth century. The idea that the declaratory theory can be traced back to natural law in that locationfore does not attract the similar scepticism today as it would have in the 19th century.The difficulty with natural law is that even if one is prepared to accept its staple fiber tenet, that there indeed are self-evident principles of ethics, it is by no nitty-gritty obvious that every situation that requires a judicial decision is one in which such fundamentals are at issue. Consider, for example, the well-known case of Entores v Miles Far East Corp (1955). This concerned the formation of a contract by telex machine, in the very early long time of this technology.Previously most formal business transactions would have been carried out by post the postal rule was and still is that if soul A offers to contract with soul B, thence the contract is formed when Bs letter of acceptance is posted to A. This is the case even if Bs acceptance never even reaches A. When considering the use of telex, the court had to decide whether the same principle could be applied to telex as to post, that is, whether a telexed acceptance was effective on sending, or on receipt. The leading judicial decision in Entores was given by Denning LJ.In his judgement he does not lift to any existing case law, or any legal principle. Instead, he says that it is simply reasonable and obvious that a telex must be received to be effective. If the declarative theory is correct, then Dennings judgement cannot be creating law it must be declaring what the law is. But since he does not refer to any existing law, it must, presumably, be derived from universal principles. Now, a advocator of natural law may believe it is self-evident that, for example, murder and impair are wrong.But it takes a real leap of faith to believe that there are principles of natural law at stake in decision making when a telexed contract is formed. The reality, of agate line, is that when Entores was take heedd, no-one really wanted to hit the postal rule extensive to a new technology. Dennings judgement is an entirely pragmatic one. It does not require any high principles to be considered. In summary, the declaratory theory is predicated utterly on acceptance of a natural law view of jurisprudence, not just for fundamental principles of ethics , scarcely for everything.This, I suggest, is just too much to swallow. Why the declaratory theory produces droll results Law students generally know astir(predicate) the retrospectivity of the declaratory theory but it doesnt run acrossm to be well still that this is not a doctrinal matter, or something that can be argued either way, it is an inevitable conclusion of the declaratory theory. If a judicial decision cannot create new law, then when the judge declares the law, as a matter of explicit logic he is declaring what the law always was. In the Entores example discussed above, this does not create a problem.It established that the use of telex had certain legal consequences, but since telex was only just coming into use when this decision was made, the fact that Denning was declaring what the law was is of no consequence. It is purely a matter of academic discussion whether the postal rule would have applied to telex in, say, the 15th century. It is, surely, of not pract ical consequence. Perhaps the first occasion on which the full innuendos of the declaratory theory had to be confronted squarely by a court was in the case of Kleinwort Benson v Leicester CC.Here, the House of lords had to rule on what should have been, for a court of this standing, a routine matter. The question at issue was whether bullion was recoverable in a restitution action, if it was paid from one fellowship to another in a demeritn understanding of law. It had always been the case that money paid under of a misunderstanding of fact was recoverable. It was widely believed that the inability to reclaim money paid under a drop away of law was unjust, and incompatible with other legal principles and other jurisdictions.Both parties to the case, and all fiver of the law lords, were in agreement on this point it should be practicable to recover money paid under a slew of law. The discrimination was on whether the decision that it was recoverable should apply only to new cases, or to past cases. Kleinwort Benson, a bank, had already paid its money to the suspect local authority. It therefore argued that the decision should operate retrospectively, so it could reclaim its money. The Local Authority, on the other hand, argued that the decision should not have retrospective effect.The problem was that if the issue were decided in favour of the claimant bank, it must have retrospective effect. This is a direct consequence of the declarative theory. After all, if the law at time T1 was X, and it is ulterior changed at time T2 by judicial declaration to Y, then the effect of that declaration is to deem that the law at T1 was Y as well. Of course, no-one at time T1 knew this, and so a decision made on the soil that the law was X, not Y, was necessarily mistaken. You may be wondering wherefore this would have such dramatic consequences.Well, a potentially super take of businesses could suddenly find that the they had grounds for litigation arising fro m things that happened in the distant past, and which they had no way of knowing at the time would be actionable. No-one would wish to see a barrage of ancient, poorly-remembered cases dragged up before the courts in the hope of gain. For technical reasons which I dont have space to explain here, the Limitations Act would not retain this. So the Law manufacturing businesss were faced with a problem.They could decide justly, in favour of the claimant bank, by ruling that it could recover its money, and accept the inevitable problems that the retrospectivity of its decision would bring. Or it could decide against the claimant, and avoid the problems, but at the expense of leaving in place an unjust and knockd rule of law. It was simply not open to the judges to change the unjust law, without the change being retrospective, unless they were prepared to openly outpouring the declarative theory. It is interesting to see how the various judges attempted to hand with this problem.It s hould be noted from the outset that all the Law Lords in Kleinwort Benson agree that, in practice, judicial decisions do change the law, rather than simply declaring it. No-one suggested for a moment that the declaratory theory was actually true. For example, Lord Goff says It is universally prize that judicial development of the common law is inevitable. If it had never taken place, the common law would be the same now as it was in the reign of King Henry II However, there was very little transport for making an official pronouncement to that effect.We will discuss possible reasons for this later. Lord Browne-Wilkinson proposed a judicial damage-limitation act upon. He suggested that although the declaratory theory should be upheld, it could be prevented from giving rise to actions arising out of past conduct. retrospection cannot falsify archives if at the date of each payment it was settled law the claimants were not drudge under any mistake of law at that date. The ulteri or decision could not create a mistake where no mistake existed at the time.In other words, what he seems to be saying is that although the claimants did in fact err in law, they had not made a mistake of law, so they could not reclaim their payments. This is quite a neat trick, because it upholds the revered declaratory theory, while preventing it giving rise to an undesirable situation. However, it does rely on judge that there are two different metas of mistake of law. One meta occurs when a somebody misunderstands the law that actually subsists at the time he applies it, and which continues to subsist.The other meta occurs when a person correctly understands the law at the time he made the decision, but his understanding was later made wrong by a judicial decision. Even if one accepts this arbitrary and unfounded distinction, it seems unsurmountable to avoid the conclusion that it is unjust. If a person makes a mistake of law, and the law remains the same, then the mistaken p erson can reclaim any money paid as a result of that mistake. On the other hand, a person who later finds that he was mistaken as a result of judicial decision cannot reclaim anything.Yet the latter person is pure his decision has been wronged by later events beyond his control. The former person could at least (in theory) have discovered what the law was. The effect of the Browne-Wilkinson solution is to kick the bucket the declaratory theory intact, at the expense of justice and common sense. Lord Goff showed, perhaps, the greatest reverence for the declaratory theory I can see no good reason why your Lordships House should take a step which, as I see it, is inconsistent with the declaratory theory of judicial decision as applied in our legal systemAs a result, he was prepared to allow a person to recover money paid under a decision in law which was correct at the time, and later shown to be false. In his analysis, the claimant was labouring under a mistake of law, but simply di d not know it. Lord Goff correctly analysed the effect of the retrospectivity of the declaratory theory, and allowed it to stand despite the preposterous results it engenders. Lord Hoffman recognised the problems that would follow from finding for the claimant, but decided that they were a price worth paying for doing justice in the particular case This may suggest that your Lordships should leave the whole question o the legislative body There is obviously a strong argument for doing so, but I do not think that it should prevail over the desirability of giving in this case what your Lordships consider to be a just and principled decision. Lord Hope decided along much the same lines as Lord Goff. Of the five Law Lords, Lord Lloyd was the only one to criticise the declarative theory It follows that the House of lords is doing more than develop the law. It is changing the law, as common sense suggests If this view of what happens is inconsistent with the declaratory theory of the c ourts function, then it is time we said so.It always was a fairy tale. And For myself, I would want to allow the appeal, if I could, avoiding the effect of retrospectivity. But as that is not to be, I consider the second best course is to leave the abolition of the mistake of law rule to Parliament. He seems to be saying that a decision for the claimant, coupled with the effect of the declaratory theory, will produce results so bizarre and unpredictable that it ought not to be allowed. In other words, the price of doing justice in this case is too high.Legal retrospectivity is bad enough in the urbane law, but in the criminal law it becomes a human rights issue. condition 7(1) of the European Convention on humane Rights specifically forbids criminal sanctions for an act that did not constitute a crime at the time it was committed. In other words, however heinous we might think an act is, it cant be punished unless the offender had a way to know it was illegal. Of course, ignoranc e of the law is no defence, but the offender has to be able to know the law to be bound by it. Consider the famous House of lords case of R v R (1994).This concerned a man who rifled his wife, and based his defence on the fact that for a man to rape his wife was not, in fact, illegal. It may be condemned, it may even be wicked, but it was not at that time illegal. If a man had approach a solicitor in 1990 and said Look, Im thinking of raping my wife, is that illegal? a equal solicitor may well have said Well, of course I wouldnt apologise it, but the balance of authority is that it isnt actually illegal. He could have cited authorities going back to the 16th century to back this up.At this time, there was increasing pressure on Parliament and the courts to overturn this unedifying principle of law, but when R was heard, no action had been taken. To cut a long story short, the House of lords decided that matrimonial rape was illegal, reversing a 400-year tradition. Everyone, with the elision of the defendant, heaved a sigh of relief. Later that year, the decision was put on a statutory basis, which appeared to settle the matter once and for all. The fly in the pick is our old friend retrospectivity. The decision in R was not that marital rape was illegal, but that it had always been illegal.Again, the court had no power to decide otherwise. And this fashion that an octogenarian who raped his wife in the 1940s could now be prosecuted. You may sapidity that this is a just conclusion you may feel that rapists should get their just deserts. However, the fact remains that we would be punishing a person for something which was not illegal at the time, and which he would have no way of knowing was ever going to be illegal. The social conditions of the time may not even have led our hypothetical defendant to think he was doing anything wrong.But he could still be prosecuted. This may clayey far-fetched, but in fact within a year of the decision in R, cases were being heard in the European Court of Human Rights (ECHR). SW v United Kingdom (1995) concerned a man who was prosecuted in 1994 for a rape he had allegedly committed in 1990. If was far from obvious that marital rape was illegal in 1990. The ECHR upheld the criminal conviction, on the basis that when the rapes occurred, the defendants could have reasonably foreseen that the criminalisation of martial rape was likely.The problem with the decision in SW v UK is that it suggests that a person must govern his behaviour, not by what the law is, but by what he predicts it will be when any consequent prosecution is bought. So, not only is ignorance of the law no defence, but ignorance of the future development of the law is also no defence None of the forgoing is intended to condone the practice of marital rape. legal retrospectivity presents the same kind of problem for any criminal offence, of any severity. Lord Diplock has suggested that the retrospectivity of judicial decisions discourages judges from correcting defects in the law.Judges have to be very conservative if they must predict not only the effect of their decisions on new cases, but the effect they would have had if made in the past. To get around this problem, the Supreme Court of the USA has select the device of prospective overruling this device allows the court to state that a decision that changes the law is not to have retrospective effect. The problem is that prospective overruling is simply incompatible with the declaratory theory. If the former comes in, the latter must go. However, as Prof.Zander says, the courts can accept that the declaratory, retrospective effect of its decisions is doctrinally correct, while at the same time letting it be known that they will decide cases on the basis of the law as would have been understood when the events occurred, not when the case is heard. This is a fudge, but credibly a workable fudge. Why is the declaratory theory so revered? In Albions Fata l Tree (1975), Douglas hay argues that the decline in formal religious observance in the eighteenth century left a power vacuum to be change by the law.For law to command the respect of society in the way that the church had done, it was necessary that it be seen as something above and beyond its practitioners The precise attention to forms, the dispassionate and legalistic exchanges between counsel and the judge, argued that those administering the laws submitted to its rules In short, its very inefficiency, its nonsense(a) formalism, was part of its strength as ideology. Such an ideology would be undermined, of course, if it were seen that law were nothing more than the creation of ordinary people.It was the job of the legal duty to form an elite, and thereby shield the ugly reality of lawmaking from national scrutiny. While this argument may have had validity in the 18th century, it is not at all easy to see that it stands up in the 21st century. To respect the law, we dont necessarily need to view it as having ghostlike origins. Moreover, since the 18th century the development of the law has increasingly been effected by statute. No-one predicts Parliaments legislative programme to be to be guided by anything more than the views of society as expressed through the ballot box.Nevertheless, while most judges tacitly accept that their activities have the effect of lawmaking, relatively a few(prenominal) have been prepared to criticise the declaratory theory in public. Lord Reid is usually credited with first describing the declaratory theory as a fairy tale in a 1972 article The judge as law-maker in JSPTL he described the Aladdins cave in which those with a taste for fairy tales expect the common law to be found. However, he was not the first potent judge to cast doubt on the declaratory theory. For example, Lord Radcliffe wrote in the Law Society Gazette in 1964 here was never a more sterile controversy than that upon the question whether a judge m akes law. Of course he does. How can he help it? Such comments are, to say the least, unusual. Prof. Atiyah is probably the most outspoken critic of the modern judicial attitude to the declaratory theory. In Judges and Policy (1980 ILR 346) he identified five reasons for its keep existence. First, it is to the advantage of the judge if he can, in a difficult case, quash any criticism of his own decision onto the law as a higher principle.As Atiyah says, of course, this can be seen as a shabby attempt to turn off responsibility. Nonetheless, the job of a judge is difficult enough, without having to deal with personal attacks on his decisions. Lord Devlin has suggested that judges will occasionally hint to claimants that they wish they could find otherwise, but are bound by the law. Second, it is generally accepted as a constitutional principle that it is the role of the legislature to make law, and the role of the judiciary to interpret it in specific cases. Where judges do make l aw, they should do so within narrow constraints.There is undoubtedly some rightfulness in this principle. The most famous exponent of judicial creative thinking in modern times is almost certainly Lord Denning. His view was very much that it was the job of the judge to do justice if that meant that principles of law had to be solidifying to fit, that was a price worth paying. The problem is that his decisions do not generalise. It is often difficult for later judges, reading his reasoning, to determine whether the decisions he made are based on law that ought to be applicable in other cases, or to fact situations particular to the case under consideration.This is evidenced by the fact that many of the principles that he established by doing the right thing in a particular case have come to be misapplied in later cases, and have had to be circumscribed by later judges. For example, his decision in Solle v Butcher (1949) that a contract could be set aside on straightforward grounds when entered under a mutual mistake, did justice in the case itself. This decision was followed in a large number of cases, but it was never entirely clear what would amount to equitable grounds.Finally, in 2003 the case of The Great Peace more or less demolished the entire concept of mistake in equity and put this class of law back where it was 50 years ago. Even if judicial creativity can do justice in the present case without conciliatory later decisions, there are other reasons why judicial creativity should be constrained. Judges are only able to deal with cases they hear it is difficult for them to take a wider view of any issue. Judges are not well-placed to make decisions that involve elements of social policy.In addition, arguably judges are drawn from a much narrower section of society than MPs, and therefore less representative. Third, Atiyah argues that judicial lawmaking is tolerated only because it is not exercised openly. Lord Devlin has argued (Judges and lawmake rs 1976 39 MLR 11) that if the courts are given, or arrogate to themselves, the power to make decisions without retrospective effect (and thereby demolish the declarative theory) this will amount to an approval to engage in judicial law-making in the large.While we accept that development of the law requires an occasional exercise of judicial creativity, the fact that it has to be done on the sly means that it wont be done all that often Paddling across the Rubicon by individuals in disguise is better than the bridging of the river by an army in akin with bands playing. Atiyahs fourth argument is that many judges themselves have a dewy-eyed and simplistic view of their own lawmaking role.They frequently speak or write as though the only alternative to a slavish devotion to the declaratory theory is the wholesale abandonment of the article of belief of reason and the separation of powers. Judges frequently invoke Seldons old chestnut about the law varying with the length of the Lord Chancellors foot as a reason for their own conservatism. However, there is no reason to assume that a disavowal of the declaratory theory need signal the end of the doctrine of precedent (it has not done so in the USA), or the breakup of the separation of powers.The fifth argument is that public respect for the judiciary depends on their strict and evident impartiality. If the judge was seen to create or change law, the implication is that the judge prefers one view of law to another. But, as Atiyah says, there is no reason to believe that the public will respect a judge that is impartial but unjust, more than one that is partial but fair. Judicial adherence, at least in public, to the declaratory theory may be for the very best of motives.However, in a well-educated, democratic society, it is doubtful whether it is ever appropriate for the governing classes to espouse one point of view in public, and a different one in private. Not only is it intellectually dishonest, it is d oubtful whether it is necessary. Moreover, it is a strategy that is tall(a) to work for much longer. It seems unlikely that the public will be moved to increased confidence in the judiciary, when it becomes obvious that the judiciary have practised a paternalistic and sponsor form of misinformation for all these years.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.