Saturday, September 21, 2019
Theory of Relativity and Pathological Science
Theory of Relativity and Pathological Science In March of 1918 Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington and his assistant E. Cottingham, went to the island of Principe off the West Coast of Africaââ¬âwith a second party stationed in Sobral, Brazilââ¬âto prepare for an experiment that would observe a total eclipse of the sun, and provide conclusive proof of Einsteinââ¬â¢s theory of relativity.[1] On 29 May 1919 they photographed a solar eclipse providing the basis for Eddingtonââ¬â¢s claims of proving Einsteinââ¬â¢s theory. The results of the experiment caused an international sensation, with Eddington being credited as the man who finally verified Einsteinââ¬â¢s revolutionary theory. Recently, the experiment and its results have been the subject of debate. Eddingtonââ¬â¢s methods and the nature of the experiment have cast doubt over its validity. Considered within Irving Langmuirââ¬â¢s notion of ââ¬Ëpathological scienceââ¬â¢, this paper argues that Eddingtonââ¬â¢s canonical experiment displays many symptom s associated with pathological science, showing the danger of performing scientific experiments with predictions already in hand, and that have been derived from theory alone. Regarding the theory of relativity, it was agreed that according to both Newton and Einsteinââ¬â¢s theories, a strong gravitational field should have an effect on light rays. If Einsteinââ¬â¢s theory were correct, light coming from the stars should be observably more bent during a solar eclipse as they pass through the sunââ¬â¢s gravitational field than in Newtonââ¬â¢s theory. Einstein believed that a starââ¬â¢s light would be shifted twice as much. The expected displacements were 0.87 second of an arc in Newtonââ¬â¢s theory versus 1.74 seconds of arc for Einsteinââ¬â¢s.[2] Since the sunââ¬â¢s gravitational effect is much greater on light than that of the earth, a solar eclipse was the only way of experimentally verifying Einsteinââ¬â¢s predictions. On the day of the experiment several problems existed. Skies were cloudy when the pictures were taken, and many problems were associated with the equipment. However, Eddington was able to obtain some useable dat a and presented the results at a special joint meeting of the Royal Astronomical Society and the Royal Society of London on 6 November 1919.[3] The results from Sobral provided measurements from seven stars that gave a deflection of 1.98 à ± 0.16 arc seconds, with results from Principe recorded at 1.61 à ± 0.40 arc seconds.[4] As Peter Coles states, ââ¬Å"Both were within the two standard errors of the Einstein value of 1.74 and more than two standard errors away from either zero or the Newtonian value of 0.87. Einstein had hit the jackpot.â⬠[5] On December 18, 1953, Dr. Irving Langmuirââ¬âNobel laureate in chemistry in 1932ââ¬âgave a lecture at the Knolls Research Laboratory where he addressed, ââ¬Å"the science of things that arenââ¬â¢t soâ⬠, giving examples of a problem he called ââ¬Ëpathological scienceââ¬â¢.[6] Langmuir identified six ââ¬Ësymptomsââ¬â¢ of pathological science: The maximum effect that is observed is produced by a causative agent of barely detectable intensity, and the magnitude of the effect is substantially independent of the intensity of the cause. The effect is of a magnitude that remains close to the limit of detectability; or, many measures are necessary because of the very low statistical significance of the results. Claims of great accuracy. Fantastic theories contrary to experience. Criticisms are met by ad hoc excuses thought up on the spur of the moment. Ratio of supporters to critics rises up to somewhere near 50% and then falls gradually to oblivion.[7] While a case could be made that each one of these symptoms can be found in Eddingtonââ¬â¢s experiments, this paper will focus on two of them in particularââ¬ânumber two and number five. Experiments that fall into symptom number two have the common characteristic that they are very near the threshold of visibility of the eyes. The solar eclipse and the evidence it produced falls directly into this category. Collins and Pinch state, ââ¬Å"It is as though a star whose light grazed the edge of the sun would appear to be displaced by a distance equivalent to the width of a penny viewed from a mile away.â⬠[8] Problems arising from this symptom are that data is easily rejected. According to Langmuir, ââ¬Å"If things were doubtful at allâ⬠, scientists ââ¬Å"discard them or not discard them depending on whether or not they fit the theory.â⬠[9] This is exactly what Eddington did with his results from Principe. He used only two photographic plates out of a total of 26 produced. From the plates, 18 were of very poor quality. These were completely ignored in his presentation and irrelevant to the experiment. His justification for this is related to the next sym ptom of pathological science. The fifth symptom maintains that any criticisms are met by ad hoc excuses thought up at the spur of the moment. When confronted about the unused plates, Eddington justified ignoring the results by claiming they suffered from systematic error. However he was unable to produce any convincing evidence to show that this was the case. When he chose which observations to keep and which to throw away, Eddington had Einsteinââ¬â¢s prediction very much in mind.[10] The general lessons to be learned from Eddingtonââ¬â¢s work relate to the difficulties encountered when performing an experiment to verify a prediction based off theory. In Eddingtonââ¬â¢s interpretation of the observations, he ââ¬Å"seemed to confirm not only Einsteinââ¬â¢s prediction about the actual displacement, but also his method of deriving the prediction from his theoryââ¬âsomething that no experiment can do.â⬠[11] Eddington claimed to confirm Einstein because he had used Einsteinââ¬â¢s derivations in interpreting what his observations really were, with the further paradox that Einsteinââ¬â¢s derivations only became accepted because Eddingtonââ¬â¢s observations appeared to confirm themââ¬âââ¬Å"Observation and prediction were linked in a circle of mutual confirmation rather than being independent of each other as we would expect according to the conventional idea of an experimental test.â⬠[12] Henry H. Bauer argues that ââ¬Ëpathological scienceââ¬â¢ is not scientific misconduct, and not done intentionally.[13] Eddington was not purposely misguiding the scientific community. He was victim to common problems confronted by all scientists, especially physicists. As Trevor and Pinch note, We have no reason to think that relativity is anything but the truthâ⬠¦but it is a truth which came into being as a result of decisions about how we should live our scientific lives, and how we should license our scientific observations; it was a truth brought about by agreement to agree about new things. It was not a truth forced on us by the inexorable logic of a set of crucial experiments.[14] Bibliography Bauer, Henry H. ââ¬ËPathological Science is not Scientific Misconduct, (nor is it pathological)ââ¬â¢, Hyleââ¬âInternational Journal for the History of Chemistry, 8(1), 2002, pp.5-22. Coles, Peter. Einstein and the Total Eclipse. London: Icon Books, 1999. Collins, Harry and Pinch, Trevor. The Golem: what everyone should know about science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Langmuir, Iriving. ââ¬ËPathological Scienceââ¬â¢. Trans R.N. Hall. Colloquium at the Knolls Research Laboratory, December 18, 1953. 1 Footnotes [1] Harry Collins and Trevor Pinch, The Golem: what everyone should know about science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p.44. [2] Peter Coles, Einstein and the Total Eclipse (London: Icon Books, 1999), p.52. [3] Coles, p.52. [4] Coles, p.52. [5] Ibid. [6] Irving Langmuir, ââ¬Å"Pathological Scienceâ⬠, trans. R.N. Hall, Colloquium at the Knolls Research Laboratory, December 18, 1953, section 3. [7] Ibid. [8] Collins and Pinch, The Golem, p.44. [9] Langmuir, ââ¬ËPathological Scienceââ¬â¢, section 3. [10] Collins and Pinch, p.45. [11] Ibid. [12] Ibid. [13] Henry H. Bauer, ââ¬ËPathological Science is not Scientific Misconduct, (nor is it pathological)ââ¬â¢, Hyleââ¬âInternational Journal for the History of Chemistry, 8(1), 2002, p.5. [14] Collins and Pinch, p.54.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.